HIV/AIDS Skepticism

Pointing to evidence that HIV is not the necessary and sufficient cause of AIDS

Defining pseudo-science: Three strikes against HIV/AIDS theory

Posted by Henry Bauer on 2011/08/16

The epithet “pseudo-science” is flung around as freely and loosely as “denialism”. In both cases, serious scholars — philosophers, sociologists, historians, and others as well — have tried but failed to devise definitions that enable applications in practice. Philosophy of science in particular spent many decades attempting to find criteria to solve the “demarcation problem”, criteria by which one could distinguish science from other pursuits. All attempts proved unsuccessful; for a summary, see Larry Laudan, “The demise of the demarcation problem”, pp. 111-27 in Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis (ed. R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan, Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1983). For a survey of specific attempts to define pseudo-science, see “Pseudo-scientists, cranks, crackpots”, chapter 8 in Beyond Velikovsky: The History of a Public Controversy.  For a detailed discussion of such attempts with respect to controversial topics like cold fusion or psychic phenomena, see Science or Pseudoscience: Magnetic Healing, Psychic Phenomena, and Other Heterodoxies.
In practice, a topic or claim (A) is called “pseudo-science” only because the name-caller believes that A is totally misguided and obviously wrong. A critique maintaining that a claim or theory B is wrong  is called “denialism” only because the name-caller believes B to be right but cannot command evidence or logic adequate to defend that belief by rational discourse.
A disinterested definition faithful to the accepted meanings of “pseudo” and “science” would be: Pseudo-science is whatever pretends or asserts to be science but is not.
The issue becomes, Who is to decide, whether something really “is” science?
In practical terms, leaving aside questions about the nature of knowledge and proof, it is a fact that there exists an identifiable “scientific community”, and one can gather empirical data about what the scientific community has or has not accepted as qualifying as science at any particular time. That latter phrase, “at any particular time”, is essential because what the scientific community accepts changes all the time: a large part of the history of science reveals how once-resisted or ignored or reviled claims later came to be regarded as great advances.
The scientific community judges claims based on what is already accepted. There are three distinct components of science: accepted facts, accepted methods, and accepted theories.
Major advances in understanding, in other words advances in theory, have often been called scientific revolutions: quantum theory, for example, or relativity. However, some advances in method, especially the development of novel instruments, are also seen by scientists themselves as revolutionary because they bring entirely new capabilities for observation or experiment: lasers, say, or infrared spectrometers, or electron microscopes. Some facts have also been revolutionary in changing scientific mindsets: that the “inert” gases are actually capable of forming compounds, say, or that genetic material consists of a double helix of DNA.
The history of science reveals that revolutions are usually resisted strenuously by the contemporary mainstream. Planck’s introduction of quantum ideas was resisted so fiercely that he later remarked that the old guys have to die off before such new ideas can gain acceptance. Charles Townes related that his Department Head accompanied by a Nobel Prize winner urged him to stop trying to construct a laser because it was impossible and his efforts were threatening to destroy the reputation of the Physics Department at Columbia University. That meteorites could have fallen from the sky was denied for a long time by the scientific mainstream.
In retrospect, however, scientists as well as outsiders forget — or never knew — that novelty is always resisted in science just as much as it is in other human affairs. For detailed discussion of such resistance, see for instance Ernest B. Hook (ed)., Prematurity in Scientific Discovery: On Resistance and Neglect (University of California Press, 2002); Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (University of Chicago Press, 1962/1970); Bernard Barber, “Resistance by scientists to scientific discovery”, Science, 134 (1961) 596-602.
The examples cited above — quantum theory, lasers, inert-gas compounds, etc. — have one thing in common: they involved revolutionary change in only one of the three aspects of science. Quantum theory and relativity were revolutionary interpretations of uncontroversial facts obtained by uncontroversial methods. Infrared spectrometers challenged no theory and no facts, neither did electron microscopy; the possibility of lasers had even been predicted by theory, albeit no one before Townes apparently envisaged a way to put that theory into practice. The double helix was a surprise, but it challenged no theory and resulted from application of well accepted methodology; compounds of inert gases challenged only oversimplified versions of valence theory, not the quantum-mechanical versions, and indeed it was the latter that inspired experimentalists to try making such compounds.
So breakthroughs that challenged only a single one of the three aspects of science had to overcome a certain amount of resistance before being accepted. Soon thereafter they became praised, and soon after that they were talked about as though they had never been resisted.
That’s how science normally progresses, change in one of its three aspects. What would happen if novelty were attempted simultaneously in two of those aspects?
“Innovation simultaneously in two facets of this intellectual troika typically causes the work to be disregarded: the relevant research community doesn’t know what to do about it, isn’t able to use it, to build upon it. This has been called ‘premature science’ (Gunther Stent, ‘Prematurity and uniqueness in scientific discovery’, Scientific American, December 1972, 84-93). Contemporary examples are the searches for gravity waves and for a magnetic monopole, both of which have so far yielded only a single claimed observation over the course of many years. There were novel facts and method in each case, as also with the classic example of Mendel’s demonstration of numerical ratios in heredity — mathematics in biology was novel in method and so the arithmetical facts were too. Wegener’s suggestion of ‘drifting’ continents broke with prevailing theory about how the Earth’s geography came about and also with accepted method or approach — he claimed as meaningful the biological and geological relationships on opposite sides of oceans. More recently Barbara McClintock’s discovery of genes moving from one chromosome to another asserted novel facts for which current theory had no explanation; so it was announced in 1951, ignored for a couple of decades, and awarded a Nobel Prize in 1983. Almost contemporaneous was Peter Mitchell’s work on biological energy mechanisms, breaking with theory and using a novel approach as well–ignored or ridiculed for about twenty years but awarded a Nobel Prize in 1978” (Science or Pseudoscience: Magnetic Healing, Psychic Phenomena, and Other Heterodoxies, p. 10).
So the historical evidence indicates that when attempts are made to change drastically and at the same time two of the three aspects of science, those attempts are ignored, perhaps even derided and denigrated; but occasionally they turn out to have been well founded and are then accepted, typically much later: some four decades in each of the cases of continental drift and Mendelian genetics.
If such “premature” discoveries have no impact on contemporary science, what happens if a claim challenges the orthodoxy not just in two but in all three aspects of science at the same time?
It gets called pseudo-science.
One instance was Velikovsky’s claimed interpretation of legendary or mythical happenings on Earth as resulting from planetary encounters (p. 152 ff. in Science or Pseudoscience: Magnetic Healing, Psychic Phenomena, and Other Heterodoxies)  or the claim that eyewitness and indistinct photography suffice to show that there exists in Loch Ness a population of large creatures never previously known to science (p. 163 ff. in Science or Pseudoscience: Magnetic Healing, Psychic Phenomena, and Other Heterodoxies).

What does all this have to do with HIV/AIDS?
Just that the initial claim that AIDS was caused by HIV satisfies these criteria for being labeled pseudo-science because it involved novelty in all three aspects of science:
An entirely novel “fact” was being claimed: immune deficiency acquired through an infectious agent that specifically destroyed immune-system cells.
One of the central methods underlying this claim had just been introduced, namely the measurement of CD4 immune-system cells. Another central method was also quite new, using the detection of reverse transcriptase as indicative of the presence of a retrovirus (incidentally, a method that soon afterwards was found to be not valid).
The theory that a retrovirus could be pathogenic at all ran counter to accepted understanding of retroviruses.

If science had been true to its customary way of judging novelties, the claim that HIV causes AIDS would have been dismissed as rank pseudo-science.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s